[200] [Footnote attached to the article title: A paper read at a conference on educating in democratic principles at St. Louis University, October 1940. Presidents and representatives of forty-one institutions of higher learning attended. We are pleased to print this paper with its careful and scholarly analysis of a subject which is receiving foremost attention by the country's educators. A university president stated recently, "I am convinced that the schools of this country have not earnestly and intelligently considered the nature of their responsibility in the transmission of our (American) culture in its basic social, political, and moral ingredients."]
What the future holds none of us can foretell, but one need not be a
prophet to see that in all probability the next five or ten years will
be among the most vitally important in the history of our nation. The
things to be done, the legislation to be adopted, the leadership to be
developed, our response to the problems and events that lie ahead of us
in the struggle between dictatorship and democracy will inevitably
modify, if not fashion, a pattern of life for us all and for our
children’s children.
We, who are charged with the responsibility of
education, have a duty whose importance cannot be overestimated. To us
has been given the opportunity, and to us has been entrusted the sacred
duty of guiding and influencing others, during the formative period of
their lives. Hence, our judgments, our words, and our actions must be
based not upon the emotions but upon real understanding of the issues
and problems with which we as a nation are confronted.
Today we are engaged in the preliminary stages of a program of national
defense. The questions confronting us transcend the interest of any
party, section, or group. They affect on the one hand our political,
economic, and cultural relations with other peoples of the world, and on
the other hand our very doctrines and traditional views concerning the
scopes and functions of our government.
It is not without profit,
therefore, that in these troubled times we recall to ourselves and to
those who come under our influence some of the fundamental principles
which if adhered to will preserve our American way of life.
During the
past few years it has become clearer that the structure of the modern
world is changing. These changes are perhaps more observable in the
political and economic order, but there is no doubt that they have
affected, or will in time affect, the foundations of the moral and
religious order as well.
[201] One of the most striking features of this changing structure is the
diminishing stature of the individual human being and the increasing
importance of the group. No longer is the state conceived of as the mere
umpire of disputes nor a policeman to suppress open discord. The modern
state, whether it be looked upon as the organ of the proletarian class
as in Russia, or a racial group as in Germany, or the incarnation of
national and political aspirations and ideals as in Italy, is considered
to be the one social reality which absorbs the individual and replaces
all other forms of social organization. It is its own absolute end and
knows no law higher than its own interests. Its claims embrace the whole
life of the individual whom it insists upon moulding [sic] and guiding from
the cradle to the grave, in order that it may make him the obedient
instrument of its will.
This, of course, is one answer to the perennial problem which has
confronted human beings from the beginning of social life—the problem,
namely, of coordinating the forces of liberty and authority so as to
attain the highest degree of social happiness. But it is an answer which
is not acceptable; the answer of tyranny. A problem is not resolved by
suppressing one of its terms. However vague and ill defined our concepts
of authority and liberty may be we realize at once that they are at the
same time complementary and opposed: opposed in the sense that they
undoubtedly restrict each other; complementary because they really
support and protect each other. Unrestricted liberty is abusive license;
while unlimited authority necessarily implies the negation of both
liberty and authority as well as the destruction of society. Liberty and
license are as far apart as liberty and tyranny; indeed license breeds
tyranny. It would be no exaggeration to say that the essential question
for every social group is that of combining liberty and authority
properly.
In all discussions concerning the relations of the individual and the
state we find, I think, that the source of differences of opinion will
be found in our varying ideas of what human nature is. As Aristotle
warns us of the danger of a little error at the beginning of
philosophical discussions so from this source momentous consequence can
grow.
There are, I think, two fundamental positions which may be taken
concerning the nature of man. According to one, man is the product of a
material evolutionary process, or man, nature and that entity which some
thinkers are pleased to call God are identified in the same reality
which is undergoing a process of emergent evolution. If this is true,
then, of course, the whole Christian point of view is a delusion. The
human being is not the result of creation nor may he look forward to
union with God. He has no inalienable rights resulting from his divine
origin and destiny, but he is completely subordinated to the state or [202] organized group which is the highest manifestation of the emergent
absolute. Right and wrong and the laws commanding the one and forbidding
the other are no longer based on eternal plans but merely represent the
exigencies of an ephemeral situation.
The other fundamental point of view can, I think, be summed up in the
memorable words of the Declaration of Independence, "We hold these
truths to be self-evident—that all men are created equal; that they are
endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights; that among
these are life, liberty, and pursuit of happines [sic]. That to secure these
rights, governments are instituted among men, deriving their just powers
from the consent of the governed; that whenever any form of government
becomes destructive of these ends, it is the right of the people to
alter or to abolish it and to institute a new government, laying its
foundation on such principles and organizing its powers in such form, as
to them shall seem most likely to effect their safety and happiness.”
In this passage, I think, we find, to a large extent, the gist of our
philosophy of government. First of all, our attention is called to the
fact that we are children of God, created by Him and endowed with
certain inalienable rights; rights which are given to us as so many
means of returning to Him. We are brought face to face with two basic
truths, our own human dignity and our divine destiny, and in these
truths lie the explanation of all rights.
We are made by God in His own image and likeness and are destined to be
happy with Him for all eternity. Indeed we are given life in order that
we may freely pursue and attain everlasting happiness. In other words
there are at least three basic rights which man may rightly claim in
virtue of a divine heritage. They are life, liberty, and pursuit of
happiness.
This is the doctrine that our Declaration of Independence sets forth. It
asserts, moreover, that governments (in God’s plan at least) are not
instituted for their own selfish ends, but that they are instituted by
men under the influence of a natural urge which impels them to live in
society in order to secure and protect their rights and to attain their
safety and happiness.
In other words the objective of man’s existence, although it means
personal individual effort, is not to be attained by him in isolation
from his fellows. By means of mutual assistance and cooperation with his
fellowmen, man can arrive at a fuller actualization of his powers and
capacities than would ever be possible by his own unaided efforts. His
needs cannot be met or safeguarded except in the broader frame-work of
civil or political society. Hence, civil society or the state is a
normal postulate of man’s nature and destiny, an institution whose very
raison [203] d'etre is the procuring of those advantages which correspond to the
social nature of man, and hence to the intentions and plans of the
Author and Creator of that nature.
The question, however, which concerns us more directly at the present
moment is that of the limits of the authority of the state or organized
group, or more generally the relations between the individual human
being and the group of which he is a part. Admitting the evident
difficulty of fixing the limits to civil authority in many specific
cases, still there are some principles that may help as guides to their
solution.
In the first place it is true that the human being is an individual and
as such is a part of the group, but the human being is something more
than an individual—he is a person, that is, an individual of a free,
rational nature and, as such, self-directing and master of his own acts.
His dignity comes from the fact that he is a person, not from the fact
that he is an individual.
The state, on the other hand, is not a mere collection of identical
irresponsible individuals; it is an organism involving the mutual
dependence and responsibility of its members. It does not exist merely
as an instrument to serve man’s needs and desires. It is an order, a
sacred order if you will, in which and by which human activities are
conformed to the Law of God. It is, in other words, a social expression
of God’s will.
The end or purpose of the state is, of course, the attainment of the
temporal felicity of all its members by the cooperation of all. By
temporal felicity is meant peace and prosperity or, to use the
Scholastic expression, the "bonum commune,” that ensemble of conditions
necessary for its members’ or subjects’ well-being and happiness. Now
this common good in the temporal order is not only material but moral in
its scope. While it has a distinctive character and integrity of its
own arising from its temporal end, it must not be forgotten that such an
end in the Christian view is not final but intermediate. It is true
that the function of the state is not precisely to guide men to Eternal
Life, still its function is essentially subordinate to that ultimate end
and, hence, in a very true sense it does foster the beginnings of
something which transcends its own nature. It may be said, therefore,
quite correctly that its purpose is to aid men to arrive at the
perfection of which they are capable and not merely to aid them but to
direct them and direct them authoritatively.
It seems obvious that no society, whatever its character, can accomplish
its task unless it possesses authority to repress abuses and direct its
members to the ends for which its was instituted. There can be no
society without authority; and since human nature and the Author of [204] nature demand society, they require also the authority. Without
attempting a complete analysis of the functions of authority we may
describe it according to the common concepts as a moral power or right
residing in a person to issue commands which are to be taken as rules of
conduct by the free will of other persons.
It is to be noted: (1) That authority is not an impersonal necessity; it
resides in a lawgiver. (2) It is not to be confused with physical force
or coercion. Coercion may become an instrument of authority (as may
persuasion) but it is not to be identified with authority as such. Such
an identification leads logically to the conclusion that "might makes
right." (3) Authority is not a mere substitute for deficiencies on the
part of those ruled by it so that if deficiences [sic] were to disappear
authority would vanish. Indeed if this were so, then theoretically
anarchy would be the best government.
The essential function of authority is to provide a fixed principle
assuring unity of action in a social group. Even supposing a group of
adults, all intelligent and of perfect good will, that is, not
handicapped by deficiencies, authority would still have its place. The
group is aiming at some objective which will be a common good for all.
That is part of the very concept of society. Such an object obviously
demands common action arising from some decision which binds all the
members. Such a decision obviously may be the unanimous agreement. But
there can never be any guarantee of unanimity of judgment; it is always
precarious and casual. Any member can disagree with the others. Hence
the unity of action required by the pursuit of the common good will be
ceaselessly jeopardized unless all agree to follow one decision and only
one, whether issued by a single individual or a selected part of the
group. To submit to the legitimate and reasonable requirements of civil
society is to obey the order of human nature in the same sense that it
is obeying the law of man’s nature to put into practice the essential
duties of family life and to respect the property and rights of others.
The human mind, however, seems to find it exceedingly difficult, if not
impossible, to face an antinomy without worshipping one or the other of
its terms. Unfortunately there is a tendency among many to overemphasize
the antinomic character of liberty and authority, while overlooking
their complementary character. There seems to be a widespread acceptance
of the assumption that growth of freedom and the decay of authority are
synonymous terms; that we can have one only at the expense of the other
but not both. That is why the world has oscillated between the extremes
of apotheosizing the individual and deifying the group. It is not and
cannot be true that we are doomed to fluctuate between tyranny and
unbridled license.
[205] The exercise of authority is not necessarily an unreasonable invasion of
personal liberty. The end of social life is not merely to preserve and
extend freedom of choice. Freedom is not really an end in itself but a
means to something else—happiness.
On the other hand, if all individual autonomy, all individual freedom of
choice, is completely merged and lost in the autonomy of the state,
then the person becomes a mere sacrifice to social utility. Nor do I see
how this sacrifice can be logically avoided if one remains on the plane
of pure naturalism. Without ultimate reference to God it seems to me
impossible to rescue the individual from complete immersion in the group
because on the naturalistic assumption that the community is the
absolute, the highest good, man is necessarily and totally subjected to
the community. Today unfortunately many states, even some who try to
reject the label totalitarian, seem to think that man is made for the
state and derives all his good from the state. This is totalitarianism
however labeled, and I must confess it is a perfectly logical
consequence of the assumption of a humanity without God.
The Christian interpretation of man and society is based on the fact
that reality transcends the material, the temporal, the purely natural;
and that the whole temporal order is subordinated to spiritual ends.
This does not mean that the temporal and material is of no importance—much less evil, nor does it mean that matter and spirit, time and
eternity, nature and supernature are identifiable. But it must never be
forgotten that the common good in the temporal order is not the ultimate
end of man’s activities. The temporal order is essentially subordinated
to the extra-temporal and the goods of this life to the eternal
interests of human personality. It is only when we appreciate this
alternating rhythm of subordination that we perceive the true status of
the individual human being. Considered as an individual or a part of the
temporal order he is properly subordinate to the order as a whole. That
is why it may be perfectly right and just that he should surrender his
temporal goods and, if necessary, even his life for the welfare of the
community. That is why the community may and perhaps should impose upon
him, as a part of the whole, many restraints and sacrifices. But there
is a limit beyond which the state or community cannot go. They cannot
infringe upon the eternal interests of those human beings who are
subordinate to them only from one aspect. States and nations are
creatures of time. They have existed and passed away, but the souls of
those men and women who once lived in them will exist for all eternity.
This concept of the state as an institution, complementing the
individual powers of man, offering him a proper environment for the
fuller development of his personality and a safeguard for the rights
which [206] flow from his nature, protects him from the extremes of both state
absolutism and exaggerated individualism. There are many today who, like
Hobbes and his leviathan or "mortall [sic] God,” look upon the state, the
civil power, as the sole source of man’s rights and duties, who make
temporal welfare the exclusive object of all laws and the standard of
all morality. It is this absolute subordination of the whole personality
of its citizens which marks the absolute state as an inhuman despotism.
Either the state is omnipotent and can do everything or it cannot. If
it can, you have despotism under the dictatorial, oligarchic, or
democratic form, benevolent or not as may be, but despotism for all
that. If it cannot, then there is something beyond its power.
The dilemma which confronts the modern man is not merely a choice
between rival economic or political systems. The question is much deeper
and more complex. The choice, as Christopher Dawson says, is between
the mechanized order of the absolute or totalitarian state (whether it
be nominally Communist or Fascist or something else) or a return to that
order which asserts the primacy of the spiritual, that is the
subordination of the state and of the whole temporal order to spiritual
ends; a return to that concept of humanity as a great community or
republic in which all work out their final destinies under the rule of
God. However fantastic a dream this may appear to the modern mind, it is
a concept which was once accepted without question as a principle of
the European social order and the foundation upon which our western
culture has been built.
---
Source: Thurber M. Smith, S.J., "Education for Democracy," Jesuit Educational Quarterly 3, no. 4 (March 1941): 200–
No comments:
Post a Comment
All comments ad hominem or deemed offensive by the moderator will be subject to immediate deletion.