A conference held at Goldsmiths College in 2007 is regarded as the founding moment of Speculative Realism; its earliest protagonists were Ray Brassier, Iain Hamilton Grant, Graham Harman, and Quentin Meillassoux. [...]
One salient point of agreement between these positions is the recourse to, or revision of, Kantian thought. They argue that the primacy of epistemology over ontology that has dominated philosophy since Kant leaves it stuck in perpetual scrutiny of the conditions of thinking. The Speculative Realists, by contrast, assume that the world is independent in some way of our conceptualizations of it. The very fact that the “thing in itself” is unknowable, as Kant declared, is supposed to make it suitable as an object of speculation. An operation Shaviro describes as a leap into fundamental uncertainty.
[The article itself]
Modern Western philosophy – at least since Immanuel Kant
published his “Critique of Pure Reason” in 1781 – has tended to
privilege epistemology over ontology. Ontology is concerned with the
nature of being, with defining, on the most basic level, what is. Epistemology, in contrast, is concerned with how we know whatever
it is that we know. It scrutinizes the grounds and limits of our
ability to know the world. To say that epistemology must come before
ontology is simply to point out that, in order to make assertions about
what the world is like, we must be able to give grounds for these
assertions, to explain how we can know that they are true. Kant observed
that the philosophy of his time was unable to provide such grounds.
Either it was dogmatic, claiming to discover metaphysical
necessity by pure logical deduction, untethered to observation or
empirical evidence; or else it was sceptical, grounded in
empirical facts and in subjective experience, but unable to generalize
beyond these particular facts and that immediate experience. Against
both of these tendencies, Kant insisted that philosophy must start by
scrutinizing, and thereby accounting for, its own foundations. If it
failed to do this, and instead launched directly into metaphysical
speculation, then only nonsense would result. For Kant, and for most
philosophers ever since, we can only claim to know something (rather than just believing something blindly) when we can explain how we have come to know it, and what justifies our claims that it is true.
In principle, this priority of epistemology over ontology
seems unexceptionable. But in practice, it has become quite problematic.
For it means that we end up talking not about things in the world that
we encounter, but rather about our own process of encountering them.
Kant insists that “things in themselves” are unknowable; all we can
really be sure of is phenomena – how things appear to us.
In the centuries since Kant, this has become a sort of common sense.
Today we take it for granted that we can never see things as they really
are, because we can never escape the distorting lenses of our own
impositions on the world. Today, these impositions have gone beyond
Kant’s categories to include such things as language, our particular
cognitive mechanisms, and our cultural biases and ideologies.
Epistemological reflection is important, because it makes
us aware of our own prejudices and otherwise unquestioned assumptions.
But at the same time, ironically, such reflection makes it nearly
impossible for us to escape from these biases and assumptions. We are
trapped inside our own perspectives, unable to take a view from any
where else. Now, it is indeed important and necessary for us to worry
about the danger of making over everything – other people, other living
entities, and other things in the universe – in our own image. But the
price we pay for averting this danger is that we end up speaking only
about, and only to, ourselves. When this process is pushed far enough,
we come to believe that the world is just an arbitrary social or
linguistic construction, that it consists only of what we ourselves have
put into it. For the late-twentieth-century postmodern philosophy of
thinkers such as Richard Rorty, and, in a more subtle/complex way,
Jacques Derrida, there is no way to escape from this straighjacket: All
we can do is point it out, and deplore it. We can never get beyond
ourselves, so as to encounter something genuinely different.
The twenty-first-century revival of philosophical
speculation is an effort to break free of this dilemma. It seeks to undo
the Kantian privileging of epistemology – but it does this for very
Kantian reasons. Kant’s own promotion of epistemology, and his ban on
metaphysical speculation, came out of his effort to avoid both the
Scylla of dogmatic rationalism, and the Charybdis of empiricist
scepticism. The current inversion of Kant, with its demotion of
epistemology, comes out of a similarly inspired effort to avoid both the
Scylla of blind logocentrism and ethnocentrism, and the Charybdis of
infinite deconstruction and auto critique. Kant denounced speculation
because it overstepped the bounds of all possible knowledge. For today’s
new speculative thinkers, in contrast, speculation is necessary
precisely because of the limits of knowledge. There is so much
that is real, but that we cannot ever possibly know.
Twenty-first-century speculation begins where our solid knowledge ends.
Far from making dogmatic claims, this new form of speculation
paradoxically explores the space of the ungraspable, and the time of the
unpredictable.
In 2007, four philosophers presented their work at
Goldsmiths in London under the banner of Speculative Realism: Quentin
Meillassoux, Graham Harman, Ray Brassier, and Iain Hamilton Grant. They
partly knew each other and each other’s work. While they have
occasionally been perceived as a relatively homogenous group, several of
them have since renounced the rubric of Speculative Realism; and
indeed, the differences among these thinkers are so great that they
cannot be said to comprise a single philosophical school. Yet, the label
of Speculative Realism is still useful, to indicate that these thinkers
at least share an important starting point. In Harman’s words, “all it
takes to be a speculative realist is to be opposed to ‘correlationism’,
Meillassoux’s term for the sort of philosophy (still dominant today)
that bases all philosophy on the mutual interplay of human and world.”
Speculative Realism insists upon the independence of the
world, and of things in the world, from our own conceptualizations of
them. It rejects the Kantian thesis that the order of the world depends
upon the way that our minds (or our languages, or our cultures) work to
structure it. And it also rejects the phenomenological assumption of a
primordial reciprocity or correspondence between self and world, or
subject and object, or knower and known. Reality is far weirder than we
are able to imagine. Things never conform to the ideas that we have
about them; there is always something more to them than what we are able
to grasp. The world does not fit into our own cognitive paradigms and
narrative modes of explanation. “Man” is not the measure of all things. This is why speculation is necessary. We must speculate,
to escape from our inveterate anthropocentrism and take seriously the
existence of a fundamentally alien, nonhuman world.
There is not one predetermined form of speculation. [...] There is no formula to guide the process of
such speculation. Each of the speculative realist thinkers proposes a
different way to speculate about the world, as it exists unknowably
apart from us.
Ray Brassier, in his book “Nihil Unbound”, doesn’t
altogether reject Kant’s epistemological concerns, his insistence upon
categories and regulative ideals – or what today we would more likely
call norms of rationality – that govern the ways in which we can
legitimately talk about the world. But Brassier goes beyond Kant, and
engages in a form of radical speculation, when he detaches these norms
from Kant’s implicitly human-centered focus. For Brassier, Kant’s
categories, such as causality, are not structures that our own minds
impose upon the world, in order to give it some intelligible order.
Rather, these methods and assumptions are forced upon us from
outside, as we seek to approach things that are alien and opaque to our
minds. Rationality is terrifyingly inhuman. Physical science allows us
to conceptualize a world that is not in any sense made to our measure.
But the scientific project can never be complete or final, as the world
is ultimately non-conceptual and unconceptualizable. Our ideas of things
can never match up to the things themselves. For Kant, this meant that
we were relegated to – but also safely grounded within – the realm of
phenomena, or mere appearances. But for Brassier, as we incessantly
approach (but never finally reach) things in themselves, we are divested
of everything that we used to take for granted. The cosmos is radically
blank and indifferent, once it has been stripped of all the meanings,
values, and narratives that we have vainly striven to impose upon it.
Our comforting presuppositions are dissolved, and only ungrounded
speculation is left to us.
In his important book “Après la finitude”, Quentin
Meillassoux, who was a student of Alain Badiou in Paris, turns Kant
inside out and renews the need for the sort of ontological speculation
that Kant rejected, in an entirely different way from Brassier.
Meillassoux opens a frontal assault upon the “correlationist”
assumptions of Kantianism and phenomenology. He insists upon what he
calls ancestrality: The indubitable existence of the universe
prior to humanity, or to any form of life, and thereby prior to any
possibility of being observed, interpreted, or evaluated. Kant
establishes “transcendental conditions of experience,” which must
logically precede (because they are always already presupposed by) any
form of existence whatsoever. But Meillassoux argues that these
conditions themselves could only have come into existence at some point
in the history of the world; before their emergence, the universe
already existed, but was not in any sense of the term “given” to us or
organized according to our categories. In other words, the correlation
between mind and world established by Kant is itself contingent, rather
than necessary. And from this insight, Meillassoux further deduces that radical contingency is
the one and only universal necessity. It is absolutely necessary, he
says, that the world has the capacity to be other than it currently is.
Things can happen for no reason whatsoever. Even socalled [sic] “laws of
nature” may arbitrarily change or disappear. In this way, Meillassoux
claims to discover truth by means of speculation – or better, to
establish the truth of speculation. Where Kant said that “things
in themselves” were unknowable because of the limitations of our own
powers of understanding, Meillassoux says rather that this unknowability
is itself a positive characteristic of things in themselves – and that
we can know this to be the case with absolute certainty.
Graham Harman’s version of Speculative Realism, which he calls object-oriented ontology,
takes yet another approach to the being of things apart from us,
referring to thinkers such as Bruno Latour and Manuel De Landa. In a
number of speculative works, including “Guerilla Metaphysics” and “The
Quadruple Object”, Harman revises Kant, and reintroduces the need for
speculation, by both extending and exploding one of Kant’s most basic
claims. Where Kant says that we can not know things in themselves
because we can only experience them in terms of the frameworks that we
ourselves impose upon them, Harman generalizes this situation to all
entities in the cosmos. It is not just human beings, or rational beings,
who apprehend the world in particular, limited ways. The world contains
a multitude of objects, and none of these objects has access to any
other object (or even to itself) in more than a superficial manner. For
Harman, Kant is right when he insists upon finitude, or the
unsurpassable limits of our knowledge. But Kant is wrong when he claims
to establish human-centered structures that are complete and certain, at
least within those limits. We don’t impose conditions upon the world,
so much as we are trapped within our own limited ability to make sense
of the world. Kant says that we must not speculate about things that we
cannot know. Harman replies that, precisely because we cannot know
things in themselves, the only thing that is left to us is to speculate.
We cannot grasp objects cognitively; but we can allude to
objects through metaphor and other aesthetic practices. In this way we
can cherish things, even though we do not fully understand them. And
such is the route of speculation: “the real is something that cannot be
known, only loved.”
Iain Hamilton Grant, who, like Brassier, was a student of
Nick Land, presents still another version of speculation in his
“Philosophies of Nature After Schelling”. In Kant’s own philosophy, the
“transcendental conditions of experience” are pre-existing structures to
which all cognition must and needs to conform. But Grant, following the
post-Kantian philosopher Friedrich Schelling, insists that these
structures themselves cannot be taken as simply given, but need to be
generated in some way. The transcendental – that which comes before all
experience, and establishes the conditions for experience – must itself
be an ongoing process, rather than just a static product. For Grant as
for Schelling, therefore, the “transcendental” can only be identified
with the infinite, ongoing productivity of nature itself – rather than
with the finite human mind, which is just one product of nature.
Speculation is necessary, for all these thinkers, because it is the only
way in which we can seek to trace the forces, powers, and events that
generate our bodies and minds, but that remain forever beyond our minds’
and bodies’ grasp.
In sum, the speculative realists all find ways to
circumvent Kant’s prohibition of metaphysical speculation. They work to
resist the anthropocentrism that results from Kant’s privileging of
epistemology over ontology. For Meillassoux and for Brassier, the way to
overcome the constraints of Kantian epistemology is to realize that the
limitations upon possible knowledge discovered by Kant are not
inscribed within our own cognitive faculties, so much as they are
already features of things in themselves, which are irreducibly
contingent (Meillassoux) or non-conceptual (Brassier). For Harman and
for Grant, meanwhile, the privilege accorded to human cognition must
itself be put into question. Human perception and understanding are less
special than we generally believe; for they belong to a much broader
spectrum of processes of relation and causal influence. What I do when I
contemplate a ball of cotton is not far different from what dye does
when it colors a ball of cotton, or for that matter from what fire does
when it burns a ball of cotton. For Harman, these are all instances of
“vicarious contact” between distinctly separate entities. And for Grant,
they are all transformations that are driven by, but that also halt and
reify, the incessant productivity of Nature. Epistemology cannot be
given priority, because understanding and knowing are themselves caught
up within larger movements for which they cannot themselves account. All
these thinkers take up speculation, not as a way to discover higher
“dogmatic” truths, but rather as a way to explore what Meillassoux calls
the “Great Outdoors” of existence, a realm far too vast and weird, and
radically uncertain, to be subsumed by our own values and norms.
---
Source: Steven Shaviro, "Speculative Realism – A Primer," Terremoto 2 (June 1, 2015), accessed June 6, 2015, http://terremoto.mx/article/speculative-realism-a-primer/.
Source: Steven Shaviro, "Speculative Realism – A Primer," Terremoto 2 (June 1, 2015), accessed June 6, 2015, http://terremoto.mx/article/speculative-realism-a-primer/.
No comments:
Post a Comment
All comments ad hominem or deemed offensive by the moderator will be subject to immediate deletion.